Prior to Islam, the Arabs’ store
of “wisdom” comprised of proverbs and aphorisms – the results of practical
experience of mundane life, which were sometimes put in poetic verse form. They
were characterised by observation of individual facts leading to no reflection
on universals. Islam presented to them revealed knowledge but relied for its
acceptance on an awakening of the intellect and common-sense – a stimulation of
thought rather than stupefaction through a show of miraculous powers. The result
was that the early Muslims were fortified with the self-assurance that in
upholding the tents and practices of the new faith they were only following the
path of wisdom and virtue. Ere long, however, their conquests of the
neighbouring lands brought them into contact with cultured communities belonging
to other faiths, notably the Monophysite and the Nestorian Christians and the
Persians, in whose land the Greek currents of thought mingled with the Perso-Indian
tradition. Liberal social intercourse and discussions on comparative religion
brought home to the Muslims the realisation that their religious thought was
characterised by simplicity worthy only of the common-sense of practical-minded
enthusiasts. There was need for philosophical articulation and logical
formulation to match the subtleties of the Schoolman and the Dialectician.
Besides the stimulus from outside, there were certain individual problems of
faith which were pressing themselves for re-examination due to stresses and
strains within their own political and social fabric. Thus the beginnings of
philosophical thought centred around the problems of Predestination and Freewill
and the Attributes of Godhead with their bearing on Unity – the main point of
difference with the believers in Trinity and Dualism. But to proceed, the
Muslims needed a mastery of Greek philosophy – the source of what they believed
to be the tactical strength of their opponents.
During the ninth-tenth centuries
C.E. many of the treasures of Greek philosophy (Arabicised falsafa) were passed
on into Arabic through the labours of Syrian Christians under the patronage of
the Caliphs and the elite of Baghdad. Though the works of the early Muslim
thinkers rely far more on neo-Platonist, neo-Pythagorean, Stoic and the Hermetic
writings, ultimately Aristotelianism came to reign supreme. But the
interpretation of Aristotle was always based on neo-Platonic commentaries.
Moreover, there were several spurious works attributed to Aristotle. One of
them, the so-called Theology of Aristotle, based on several sections of
Plotinus’ Enneads, exercised a profound influence on Muslim thinkers. The Arab
scholars succeeded well in passing beyond the narrow limits of Nestorian studies
but perhaps it was beyond their resources to disentangle Aristotle from
neo-Platonism.
The first look by the Muslims at
Greek philosophy amply confirmed their self-assurance that Reason could not
conflict with Revelation. The towering fact of monotheism emerging from the
circles of Greek philosophy so enraptured them that they set about hastily
adopting and appropriating the new acquisition instead of critically examining
it in all its details. This is best exhibited in the attempt at parallelism
between the language of philosophy and the language of religion, e.g. the theory
of the spheres was taken over and the Intellects recognised as “angels” while
the Intellectual Light was equated with Revelation. But when all the possible
equations were exhausted it was found on deeper thought that there remained a
considerable residue representing the area of disagreement between Reason and
Revelation. It is the working of the Muslim mind, represented more by the
Persians and the Turks than by the Arabs, on this marginal area which justifies
distinctive term “Arabic Philosophy”, “Arabic” referring only to the language of
expression and to some extent to historical milieu.
The impact of philosophy gave
rise to two schools of thought among the Muslims. First, there were those who
clung to the primacy of Revelation but, in demonstrating its identity with
Reason resorted to a liberal or what appeared to them to be the “reasonable” and
the “natural” formulation of the tenets of Islam. These apologists of
Revelation, the Mu‘tazilites as they were called, went for in the pursuit of the
concept of Natural Religion until they veered themselves into a position of
antagonism to Orthodoxy. They could not resist the temptation of imposing their
Intellectual Islam on the masses at the point of the bayonet under the aegis of
their champion, the Caliph Mamun (813-33), a venture ruined them and defeated
their own purpose. However, the sanguinary showdown came only after they had
left their indelible mark on Muslim thought and shaken orthodoxy out of rigidity
forever.
Secondly, there were the
philosophers in the proper sense of the word, who believed in the primacy of
Reason but were still at pains to demonstrate its compatibility with Revelation.
For them the end of the first stage of establishing an authentic version of
Greek philosophy was reached with the first and last of the Arab philosophers,
al-Kindi (d. c.873) and the Turk, al-Farabi (d. 950). The second stage of the
formulation of a doctrinal system was completed by Ibn Sina (Avicenna, d. 1037).
The outstanding problems which these Muslim philosophers had to grapple with
were no easy ones: the Eternity of Matter, the process of the creation of the
Many from the Absolute One, His Omnipotence and Omniscience with regard to the
Universal and the Particular, Immortality of the Soul and Resurrection, and, of
course, the overall consideration of the need for, and the nature and
admissibility of, prophethood. From the orthodox point of view, the philosophers
appeared to be sceptics but where tolerated so long as they did not repudiate
Revelation outright. A strong reaction was, however, touched off by the attacks
of Ibn al-Rawandi (d. 935), a Jewish convert of questionable motives, on the
institution of prophethood. The reaction culminated in Ash‘ari (d. 935) and
Ghazali (d. 1111), both of whom exposed the unreliability of philosophy and
repudiated the same on behalf of Religion. They were, of course, accomplished in
the use of the weapons of philosophy and, in turning them against unbridled
Reason, satisfied not only the masses but also the intellectuals. Only Ash‘ari’s
accasionalism – the assertion of direct activity and creation by God and the
denial of natural causation – had a reactionary effect on the Muslim mind. It
was left to Ibn Rushd (Averroes, 1126-1198) to resuscitate philosophy by making
amends for the vagaries of the renegades and at the same time exposing the
retaliatory partisan attitude of Ghazali.
Significantly enough, Ibn
Rawandi declared himself to be depending on Indian wisdom in the repudiation of
prophethood. The Samaniyya, ie. the Buddhists, were well represented in the
cosmopolitan Abbasid society by Jarir Ibn H~azim al-Azdi of Basra, who, though
remaining within the community, invited the intellectuals of his age to his home
and argued Buddhist philosophy with them. But atheism or agnosticism constituted
a palpable heresy not only against Islam but also against Greek philosophy; it
was viewed only as a curio of philosophical thought. The attacks on the
institution of prophethood, which was equally lacking in Greek philosophy,
called forth a spirited defence especially from the Fatimid Shiites, who
believed in the divine guidance of their Imams or leaders. It was just because
of its ultimate monotheism that Hindu – as distinguished from the Buddhist –
thought had greater chance of admission within the circle of Muslim
philosophers. Aristotelianism asserted the existence of the “Unmoved Mover” but
posited Eternal Matter in a sort of Dualism with Him. It was here that the
Monism of Hindu thought attracted the Muslim thinkers strongly. Moreover, once
the existence of God is regarded as a fundamental reality, the urge to establish
some sort of communion with Him is awakened. Strictly speaking, Islam provides
for this communion only through the consciousness of the will of God during the
full course of Man’s participation in the normal life-pattern of this world. But
already under the influence of neo-Platonism, ways of contemplation – as opposed
to activity – were being explored by the Muslims when the concepts of emanation
and re-emanation came across their way. Thus pantheism was able to enter
surreptitiously and under sufficient disguise. Yet the other characteristic
features of Hindu thought such as Incarnation and Transmigration were vigilantly
kept outside. Even the excesses resulting from the concept of “Union with God”
touched off violent reaction as in the case of H~usayn Ibn Mansur al-H~allaj
(who was executed in 922). Once the contemplative ways of communion came in
vogue, the ascetic practices and the institution of the Orders were borrowed
from the Christian monks, the Hindus, whose mortification of the flesh,
nevertheless, continued to be abhorrent, and from the Buddhist sangh, whose
moral ideal of self abnegation deeply impressed the common Muslim. Remarkably
enough, even vegetarianism was dissociated from the notion of birth cycles or
mere compassion for the sentient being; it was assimilated to a much higher
ideal which made H~ayy Ibn Yaqzan, the hero of Ibn T~ufayl’s philosophical
romance, pause to think whether he was not obstructing the ordained processes of
nature by appropriating for himself the milk of the cow, which was really meant
for the subsistence of the calf, and the fruit of the tree, which was designed
for the propagation of the kind.
Philosophy also came to be
cultivated in secret societies possessing an esoteric doctrine in a political
setting. One of them, the Brethren of Purity (c. 970), became famous for a
somewhat incoherent compendium of philosophical thought collected from all the
sources and showing a marked deviation in favour of Pythagorean speculation.
Lastly, Ibn Khaldun (1332-1476),
the father of the Philosophy of History, applied the discipline to the world of
men, determining the facts of history and their proximate causes and deriving
the law governing the development of human society.
On the whole, the Arabic
philosophy is remarkable for the evolution of a peculiar approach by Reason
towards Revelation. It was fortuitous indeed that the Muslims received
Aristotelianism overgrown with Neo-Paltonism, but the synthesis which they
themselves assiduously worked afterwards remains distinctly theirs. Still more
important is the concession which Discursive Reason was ultimately compelled to
make in favour of Intuition. The example of the Muslims in reconciling Religion
with Philosophy was emulated by the Jews living in the western parts of the
Islamic world and they in turn acted as intermediaries between the Muslim
philosophers and the Western Christians. The influence of Avicenna, Ghazali,
Averroes and others, so prominent in the writings of Thomas Aquinas, ultimately
led to Christian Europe’s discovery of the lost treasure of Greek learning. |